Смекни!
smekni.com

The Specifics Of That Which Is General (стр. 1 из 3)

– A Discussion Of Rousseau’s General Will Essay, Research Paper

Rousseau’s concept of “the general will” (la volont? g?n?rale) has been generally misunderstood. It has been criticized on the one hand as a form of vacuous idealism, and on the other hand as nothing more than another name for majority rule. But the concept is, in fact, neither of these. Rousseau constructs a sophisticated and meaningful picture of the general will that manages to avoid both of these extreme positions. Situated between those two poles, it provides a solid foundation for the state that Rousseau envisions. In the role that he has assigned to it, the general will does not fall short; but that does not mean that the general will is beyond criticism. In this paper I will argue that what needs to be questioned in Rousseau’s theory is not the general will’s efficiency, but rather its possibility. In order to make this argument, my first project will be to clarify just exactly what Rousseau means by “the general will.” Taking him at his word when he says, “[a]ll of my opinions are consistent, but I cannot present them all at once,”1 I will try to piece together the many and various comments on the general will that Rousseau makes throughout the Social Contract in order to form–ultimately–a single coherent picture of the phenomenon. After that, I will raise some questions about that picture, and consider the adequacy of the foundation that it provides for a society. Then I want to take up the deeper question concerning what makes Rousseau’s general will possible. Has the criticism addressed so far against the general will been misdirected? Should it be applied, not to Rousseau’s elaborate notion of the general will, but rather to the condition of its possibility?2

1) Three Versions of the General Will

It seems to me that at least three different meanings or versions of “the general will” can be identified in The Social Contract. Each of these forms of the general will can be distinguished in terms of its subject (that which does the willing), its object (that which is willed), and its relationship to the “private will.”3 The best place to begin in order to identify and compare these three different forms is with that version of the general will that I will characterize as “ideal.”

The following is a chart demonstrating the similarities and differences of the 3 types of General Will, using the distinctions mentioned above:

Subject – That

which does the

willing. Object – That which is

willed. Relation to the Private Will.

Ideal General

Will Hypothetical

contract with all

members of

society. General Good – The

means to a particular

social end. Therefore

there are multiple

objects. No necessary relation to the

Private Will.

Originary

General Will Actual contract

with all members of

society. General Good. General and Private Will are

necessarily identical in terms

of their various objects.

Actual

General Will Majority of the

members of

society. Not necessarily the

General Good. Relationship is completely

undetermined.

A) “Ideal” General Will

This form of the general will is “general” in terms of its object. The object that is willed is the “general good,”

which is the good of all–”the general interest” (SC 155). The generality of this object is its applicability to all

the willing subjects in a given society. Whatever is willed must be in the best interests of every member of this

group; its good effects must extend to all of them universally. But, for Rousseau, there are two possible types

of “the general good” which can be willed in a way that will satisfy this requirement: the good which is the

universal end of a society; and the “goods” which are the particular means to that singular end. The object of

the ideal form of the general will is the latter (SC 153, 158-159). The ideal general will wills all of the

particular means that are required to reach the end which is posited as a society’s telos.

Thus, there are actually multiple objects belonging to this form of the general will. Each one corresponds to a

different moment in the history of a society as it confronts diverse challenges and opportunities along the way

to its final general good. For Rousseau, all the means that lead to that end constitute the particular goods–with

universal applicability–which are the successive objects of the ideal general good. Each constitutes, in its own

particular moment, the general good of a society which ought to be willed by all the members of that society.

But Rousseau acknowledges that this form of the general will may not always be found “generally” in all of

those subjects. In fact, at any given moment it may not be actually willed by any subjects at all; but he does not

think that would make any difference. In his presentation of this type of general will Rousseau relies

(implicitly) upon a Platonic distinction between the “ideal” and the “actual.” He insists that the real existence of

this form of the general will–the reality of its object, and the reality of the subject’s obligation to will that

object–would remain the same, “constant, unalterable and pure,” even if that will were completely unactualized

in practice (SC 204). The ideal general will is an ideal form. At any given moment, its particular object cannot

necessarily be located through empirical observation, for it is not guaranteed to exist in actuality. Determining

this object is a strictly rational project that requires locating oneself, as a member of a society, in the light of

that society’s overall telos, and then making decisions about particular means to that end in terms of what one

honestly knows to be the general good. What complicates this process most of all is the fact that there is no

necessary correspondence between the object of the ideal general will and what Rousseau calls “the private

will.” The private will always has a particular subject: each individual in the society (SC 177). And its object is

always the uniquely private good of that particular subject. “[E]ach individual can, as a man, have a private will

contrary to or different from the general will that he has as a citizen. His private interest can speak to him in an

entirely different manner than the common interest” (SC 150). All the private wills of the members of a society

taken together constitute the “will of all,” whose reality, (as opposed to that of the ideal general will), is always

strictly empirical. “There is often a great deal of difference between the will of all and the general will. The

latter considers only the general interest, whereas the former considers private interest and is merely the sum of

private wills” (SC 155). Conflict between the two is inevitable. The private will “acts constantly against the

general will,” Rousseau states categorically at one point in The Social Contract (SC 192). At other times he

allows that “it is not impossible for a private will to be in accord on some point with the general will”; but he

quickly adds, “it is impossible at least for this accord to be durable and constant” (SC 153). The subjects of the

ideal general will are always going to be particular, individual citizens, but because it must contend for those

subjects against the private will, the general will may not even win a majority. Thus, the ideal general will’s

objective generality, which is a function of its ideal nature, will not necessarily correspond to an empirical,

subjective generality.

B) “Originary” General Will

But Rousseau also speaks of the general will as something that is “general” both objectively and subjectively. It

is necessary for this “originary” form of the general will to exist prior to the general will in its ideal form in

order to give the latter its normative strength, and also in order to give the society whose good is to be willed a

just foundation. There must be some stage in the overall history of the general will, Rousseau argues, when the

general good of a society is necessarily willed generally by all the subjects in that society.4

Such a subjective generality is possible only when the object of the general will is identical with the various

objects of the private will. What each individual wants to will as his or her own individual good must be made

to agree perfectly with what all the people ought to will as the general good of their whole society.5 The

moment when all of these objects are identical is the moment of a society’s origination; upon it Rousseau will

build his entire state. He explains this moment in an extremely important paragraph from Book II, Chapter

IV, that deserves extensive commentary:

The commitments that bind us to the body politic are obligatory only because they are mutual, and their nature is such

that in fulfilling them one cannot work for someone else without also working for oneself. Why is the general will

always right, and why do all constantly want the happiness of each of them, if not because everyone applies the word

each to himself and thinks of himself as he votes for all? This proves that the quality of right and the notion of justice it

produces are derived from the preference each person gives himself, and thus from the nature of man; that the general

will, to be really such, must be general in its object as well as in its essence; that it must derive from all in order to be

applied to all; and that it loses its natural rectitude when it tends toward any individual, determinate object. For then,

judging what is foreign to us, we have no true principle of equity to guide us (SC 157).

Here Rousseau explains how right, justice, obligation, and social stability are all framed by the original

agreement of general and private will. This agreement permits one to trace social relations back to an interest

which is selfish–but not purely selfish. It is, at the same time, social, since its object is simultaneously the good

of the whole and the good of each individual. However, it is more than just a fortunate coincidence that

permits us to trace the genealogy of a society back to this agreement. Without it, Rousseau argues, no society is

possible at all. There is no other way of founding a society. Lacking an originary agreement or ‘contract’ which

permits the general will to be general both subjectively and objectively, there would be “no true principle of

equity to guide us.” Right and justice could not be grounded; the Rousseauan state could never get underway.

Original general will allows the state to get underway by founding the social contract. The agreement between

general and private will is, in essence, a “proto-social contract” because it already constitutes a people.6 It

unites individuals in a situation which is mutually advantageous for all, where “one cannot work for someone

else without also working for oneself.” In such a situation the “quality of right and the notion of justice it

produces” can be derived from the only sure and stable source: “the preference each person gives himself, and

thus from the nature of man.” When a group’s private interests and its general interest can be made to intersect

so perfectly, there is no longer anything standing in the way of their formation as a society. In this agreement,

the essential gesture of constitution has already taken place; all that remains is to work out the contractual

formalities.

This is where the social contract proper enters. It is commonly assumed that the only foundation of a

Rousseauan society is the social contract;7 but Rousseau explicitly denies this. While the social contract does in

fact serve “as a foundation for all other rights” he argues, “[n]evertheless, this right does not come from nature.

It is therefore founded upon convention” (SC 141). The main convention which supports and structures society

is itself based upon another convention. The general nature of all conventions ought to be such that they must

be equally beneficial to each of the parties that enters into them (SC 146-147). Concerning the social contract

in particular, Rousseau says that it requires a founding convention which will make possible that each subject,

“while uniting with all, nevertheless obeys only himself and remains as free as before” (SC 148). The

convention which can satisfy all of these requirements, and thus successfully found the social contract, is the

agreement of the general and the private will on the telos of society. This telos is the “common good” which is

the “purpose for which [the state] was instituted” (SC 153). It is the “cause” that “each people has within

itself,” which “organizes them in a particular way and renders its legislation proper for it alone” (SC 171).

Individuals in a society must be made to see the telos which is in the best interest of the entire group as

something that is also in their best interest individually and privately. Agreement on that end allows a society to

begin. For if the opposition of private interests made necessary the establishment of societies, it is the accord

of these same interests that made it possible. It is what these different interests have in common that forms the

social bond, and, were there no point of agreement among all these interests, no society could exist. For it is

utterly on the basis of this common interest that society ought to be governed (SC 153). By positing this form

of the general good as its unitary object, originary general will clears the way for the ideal general will to

follow, willing the various general goods that are the means to that end. In the history of a state, the ideal form

of the general will first emerges when the newly constituted society moves the focus of its deliberations from

the singular end which it has projected ahead of itself to the particular means which are required in order to get

to that end. At this point the correspondence between private and general will ceases, and thus, “[u]nanimity no

longer reigns in the votes; the general will is no longer the will of all” (SC 204). Thus, both the ideal and the

originary general will have the general good as their object, but not the same form of the general good. The

objects of the ideal general will are multiple, transitory, and dependent on the single object of the originary

general will, which arises from the original agreement of private and general will that founds the state.

This foundational general will is constant even if the ideal general will that follows after it is not. This

follows because each individual’s private will continues to be tied up in the original general will, and

individuals cannot ignore their private interest. “Each man, in detaching his interest from the common interest,

clearly sees that he cannot totally separate himself from it… Apart from this private good, he wants the general

good in his own interest [which is the object of original general will], just as strongly as anyone else” (SC 204).

While all subjects ought to will according to ideal general will, they cannot help but will the original general

will. To do otherwise would be to deny their rational, self-interested natures. Rousseau, who insists that his

arguments are based on “reason” and “the nature of things,” denies that such a modification of human nature is

possible (SC 146). He allows that humans are eminently capable of resisting the general good when it is

opposed to their own interest: this is the reason why the ideal general will does not necessarily enjoy subjective

generality. But when the general good appears in the guise of the private good, humans necessarily will it–

perhaps without realizing it; perhaps in spite of themselves.

Such constancy is possible, of course, only as long as the original agreement between private and

general will is preserved. As long as this correspondence between general and private will continues, it

functions as the ultimate source of a society’s vitality, “the true constitution of the state” (SC 172). This

enduring, foundational general will is the “law” which is,

the most important of all. It is not engraved on marble or bronze, but in the hearts of citizens… Everyday it takes on

new forces. When other laws grow old and die away, it revives and replaces them, preserves a people in the spirit of its

institution and imperceptibly substitutes the force of habit for that of authority… [It is] a part of the law unknown to our

political theorists but one on which depends the success of all the others; a part with which the great legislator secretly

occupies himself (SC 172).

But once the agreement of the general and the private will is shattered, society loses its foundation, and has no

guarantee of continuing. Rousseau seems to be saying that a state will persist just as long as its originary