Смекни!
smekni.com

Integrating Care And Justice Moral Development Essay (стр. 2 из 2)

Part Two: Integration of Care and Justice

The major point of this part of the paper

is to hypothesize and analyze Kohlberg’s stage three and four, along with

the transition between the two. From what I have gathered from the assignment,

the goal is to reanalyze both the stages, show their adequacies and inadequacies,

then integrate the two to form a stronger quasi-stage four. I have discussed

the stage three to four “regression” in the first part of my paper, but

this segment will be more dedicated to the integration of the stage’s details,

rather than the blatant defense of the perspective.

My first job will be to show stage three’s

adequacies. Stage three is a personification of what we all wish we could

be. Noble, strong, and almost saintly, it represents all of the qualities

that everyone wants to possess. The stage is almost entirely based upon

the idea that all people deserve to be treated with respect and dignity,

regardless of the previous actions, or outward complexion. I find that

the word “faith” seems the best to describe this stage. Faith in people

around you, and in their motives.

However, some of the shortfalls of stage

three are very aptly listed in the handout packet. It can be indeterminate,

arbitrary, idealistic, indecisive, and localized. Indeterminacy has it’s

root in the enactment of the “golden rule”. It seems so simple and easy

to discuss, but in practice, it’s execution is questionable. “Do unto others

as you would wish them to do to you.” But why does that indicate that it

is the right choice? Isn’t it a matter of personal preference? Suppose

I enjoy being beaten with a bat! Does that give me the right to do it to

someone else? This rule assumes that all people share the same interests,

likes, and dislikes. If the entire population has an aversion to physical

harm, then this rule will work. However, can’t an assailant justify his

actions by proving that he enjoys physical harm? Although morally enticing,

the golden rule does not set down concrete guidelines that should mold

people’s behavior.

Localization and the in-group also propose

a significant criticism of this view. Stage three almost mandates that

those people who surround you are the most important in the world. One

should fulfill their obligations to the in-group above and beyond all others.

In other words, you must desensitize yourself to the rest of the world’s

problems, and just deal with those that involve your direct family. How

in the world can this be considered a moral competence? You are selecting

those people for whom you will show compassion and caring, and excluding

others by rule. Unfortunately, stage three has no allowance for integrating

the social contract into moral development. Instead, it totally excludes

it with this in-group system.

To close this point, I would like to raise

the hypothesis that stage three is theoretically the best stage that can

be achieved. It assumes that people are moral by nature, and with a little

guidance, can show this in their treatment of others. The assumption is

made that regardless of perspective, there are undeniable rights and respects

that every human deserves. No matter what the priorities of each individual,

they will not infringe upon the rights of others. However, in practice

it is simply not effective. Based upon the competence achieved up until

the stage three level, it seems the best policy of interaction. But in

practice, it stinks!. It just does not function on a level that would allow

it to be the predominant

method for interpersonal relations and ethical

decision-making. The system is based upon trust and values, neither of

which people tend to put much faith into.

Stage four remedies many of the stage three

inadequacies with the introduction and assimilation of a social contract.

Many of the same ideas from stage three remain, given new functionality

and definition. For instance, the golden rule has been replaced with social

reciprocity, the idea that merit is given to good citizens. The social

system itself takes over as the primary guiding focus of the people.

Because of this new agreed upon social

contract, the holes of stage three have been filled. There is no longer

the indecisive, abstract nature of the previous stage, because a contract

has been agreed upon by the masses. Not every little niche of the policy

agrees with every person, but for the most part, it holds the beliefs of

the population. A certain “golden rule” has been put into place, with designated

actions that warrant punishment. If you do this, you will be punished accordingly.

There is no chance for arbitration (although one is able to change the

system itself, or prove their innocence through the proper channels). Rules

have been set down, agreed upon, and now enforced.

At the same time, the localization of stage

three has also been removed. The system that works to enforce this “new

golden rule” has to be agreed upon by all people. It’s flavor may change

slightly from region to region, but generally, they must all follow the

same guidelines. So, just to achieve stage four we must banish the localization

of stage three. Personal priorities then follow the system. Instead of

prioritizing the in-group above all others, a new conglomerate is formed

of everyone’s in-groups into one society. The survival of that society

is supreme, since it is the chosen protector of all these familial microcosms.

Laws, rules and regulations take over for individualistic judgement, helping

to herd everyone into the proper behavior.

With this new system, we obviously lose

some of the aspects of stage three that were most attractive. We no longer

have the family dedicated, honor above-all-else person that we did in the

previous stage. He has been replaced with someone who is now, at best,

a law abiding citizen. The principles of stage three have been incorporated,

though not fully, into the pragmatism of stage four. For instance, a lawless

or unconventional act that would not have been tolerated at stage three

would be ignored at stage four so that the integrity of the social system

would not be compromised. We lose the hardcore justice orientation, and

replace it with a more flexible society-inclusive system.

Increasing the size of anything to encompass

more increases it’s complexity. Complexity means that this system is not

only hard to maintain, but increasingly slow to acquiesce to the changing

needs of the people. It takes a lot of time to change an entire society’s

interpretations. Status-quo stagnation occurs very quickly, and reform

seemingly takes forever.

So, imagine that we could take stage four,

plop in into a blender, add some stage three, and come out with an even

better system. What would we do? This is the next question to be addressed.

Looking at stage three’s and stage four’s adequacies and areas of lacking,

we need to incorporate pieces of both into an entirely new system.

The real goal is to somehow take stage

three’s interpersonal nobility and faith, and give them to a stage four

person. At the same time, we do not want to undermine the societal interactiveness

of stage four! I believe that what we end up with is the theoretical model

of a democracy. For instance, we take stage four’s society agreed upon

contract (assuming that it is somewhat noble, as opposed to something from

the Third Reich). We now assume that an act has been committed that borders

between criminality and unconventionalism. How could we approach this?

Stage three says: “If it isn’t a threat to my immediate person, or those

who surround me, then don’t worry about it.” Stage four would reply: “What

of it’s effect on the social system, is it against the law?” What we really

need to do is combine the two perspectives. If this act is first viewed

to warrant public action (an arrest, trial, or hearing), then that should

be the course of action. It is what takes place next that is very important.

During the proceedings, each and every person must come to terms with it

in their own way. They must decide if it is destructive, constructive,

or indifferent. As a group, they must decide on the best course of action.

This way we have incorporated the individualistic judgement and nobility

of each person and fused it with societal administration. In addition,

we have allowed each person to place part of their own golden rule interpretation

into the system.

By carefully combining the features of

two very different stages, we have come up with a system that is better

suited to meeting the needs of a population. Unfortunately, it was invented

hundreds of years ago, and implemented in the United States Constitution.

Granted, it does not work perfectly, but it seems a suitable compromise

when considering the alternatives. It may be a slow process, and one that

can be abused to fit one’s needs, but it is the only one that incorporates

the individual into the molding of the system.

The final part of this paper will be dedicated

to the combination of two very different arenas of thought, the moral development

paths of justice and care. Some have argued for and against each, some

have argued for and against both. What we will try to do is to build an

entirely new moral system on the strengths of these two. Theoretically,

we should come up with a super-competent solution, one that is better than

the two individually. Rather than try to develop this step by step and

point by point (which would be intolerable after about the second line),

I’d like to just give my interpretation of what the final product would

look like. One note: the most that can be possibly asked of any person

in any system is that they give 100 percent all the time. Therefore, any

theorizing that we do is subject to the fact that people only have the

resources to accomplish certain things.

To combine the best features of two diametrically

different institutions of thought we have to first identify what those

features are. Kohlbergian justice is the pragmatic, society oriented variety

that is admittedly dedicated to preserving social systems. Gilligan’s caring

is predicated on good interaction between people. Although they sound like

they might be trying to achieve the same things, they are going at it in

two separate ways. Kohlberg wants to invent a system by which all people

know what is expected of them. Rules are proposed, agreed upon, set down,

and enforced. Each and every person knows what is appropriate behavior.

Even at stage five, the supposed highest known stage of Kohlberg’s development,

the society rates very high. There may be different ways to approach running

a society, but there is no question that there must be something running

it.

Gilligan seems to agree that people need

rules by which they can relate to one another. However, she seems to delve

deeper into the actual motivations of those rules. While obeying the regulations

of society, you must also show some sort of compassion and caring for other

people. As a trivial example, Kohlberg’s system would say that it was rude

to interrupt someone who is speaking. Gilligan would say that merely not

interrupting is not adequate. Instead, you must show interest in what that

person is trying to say. You must somehow relate with the speaker on some

level. In doing so, you not only draw more from his words, but you show

that you can identify with him.

Another feature of Gilligan’s work that

I feel should be integrated into the justice theme is that of self-care.

When put down in words it seems somewhat egotistical and self-centered.

Kohlberg would be interested in self-care only if it contributed to maintaining

society. But balancing the needs of the many, and the needs of the few

is the hardest part about effectively administering any group of people.

Some individuals will have very menial needs, others will say they require

luxuries. The key is to provide a method by which all people can fulfill

those needs. Self-care will differ significantly between even similar people.

So, rather than trying to meet their needs outright, it is better to just

provide a chance by which they can provide for themselves. Thus achieving

a balance between self-care and still allotted care for others. (I know,

I’m drawing the democracy parallelism again, sorry!)

Kohlberg provides us with the minimal framework

by which regulations maintain the necessities of people. If his guidelines

are followed, it can be said that everyone who lives by them will be at

least partially satisfied. Gilligan, on the other hand, shows us that there

is a much deeper level to which we can all aspire. Putting effort into

everyday interaction, from talking to listening, can greatly enhance every

experience. In doing so, we are not only improving the quality of our own

lives, but also the lives of those we interact with.

Another aspect of caring that I would like

to bring into the “justice world” is included in level three, the highest

level of caring. It states that there are absolutely no black or white

issues. What might be correct for one person, is not necessarily the same

for another. This would fill a huge hole in the Kohlberg moral development

system. Justice is largely criticized because it “forces” everyone into

a social group. It then slaps some rules down, and expects that they are

applicable to everyone. Gilligan states that this is not true, but rather,

everything is a shade of gray. Be careful though! This does not mean that

rules are now not applicable to anyone. Rather, it states that we must

use our judgement when considering transgressions of the law. There may

be special circumstances that need to be addressed.

Finally, Kohlberg’s critics have said that

stage five is too arbitrary. It is not easy to tell exactly how much one

owes to the social contract, or what to do with people who do not necessarily

agree with it. Gilligan would argue that there is a way to resolve this

conflict of interests through dialogue, attention, and compromise. Where

Kohlberg’s system leave opportunity for arbitration, Gilligan’s says that

there is no need. Instead of giving people a hard set of rules to live

by, or demanding their surrender to a contract, we could talk to them individually

and address the situation.

At the same time, justice maintains that

there are undeniable rules that must be obeyed. So, we are combining the

best of both worlds. Using Kohlberg’s justice orientation, we are guaranteeing

the sanctity of all those who have already agreed to the social contract.

Concurrently, we’re taking it upon ourselves to listen to a non-supportive

person, and possibly come to a small compromise to fit their needs.

In conclusion, it seems that there is definitely

a way to combine the Kohlberg justice theme and the Gilligan caring theme

of moral development. Mr. Kohlberg provides a method to police a society

that does not include 100 percent utopian citizens. Ms. Gilligan gives

us the ability to relate to each and every person, as a person. She indicates

ways that we can identify with their perspectives, understand their needs,

and compromise. Although the real world seems infinitely more complex than

either of these models, they bear a frightening resemblance to real societies

and real people. Maybe someday, a perfect model will be constructed, judged

by a perfect path of moral development. Until then, I hope that I have

found a good combination of these two ideas.

One last side note: I think I could spend

weeks typing a paper on this subject. There are thousands of facets of

each system that could fit into the other’s potential flaws. However, I

think I’ve been long-winded enough as it is. I have tried to make my points

as succinct and reasonable as possible, but without sacrificing exactly

what I wanted to say. Thank you for your patience.