Смекни!
smekni.com

Augustine And Freedom Essay Research Paper Augustine (стр. 2 из 2)

the persuasion of a neighbor . . . Both, however, are voluntary.”24 Sin issues from within and

without. There are two mediums through which sin enters: (1) the bodily senses and (2) evil

desires (cf., I Jn. 2:14-15; Jam. 1: 14). In either case the will is utilized. “Sins . . . are to be

ascribed to nothing but to their own wills, and no further cause for sins is to be looked for.”25

That persons are both impotent and ignorant does not make them less guilty before God.

These are the conditions under which unregenerate creatures exist. Ignorance and impotence

are conditions, not causes.

Analogously, a drought is not the cause of hunger; lack of food is. The drought may be the

condition under which hunger occurs, but it is not the cause of hunger. So too, God created

the condition (viz., freedom) from which humans could move closer toward him. Adam

voluntarily chose otherwise and, hence, became guilty. The cause of the guilt is the misuse of

the condition (freedom). In essence, God caused the condition, Adam abused it and,

therefore, became guilty.

Why should not the Author of the soul be praised with due piety if he has given it

so good a start that it may by zeal and progress reach the fruit of wisdom and

justice, and has given it so much dignity as to put within its power the capacity

to grow towards happiness if it will?26

Though God gives freedom at creation he is not to be charged with its misuse. “The soul was

not created evil because it was not given all that it had power to become.”27 The purpose for

which God gifted his creatures with freedom was that they might live righteously. God is

exonerated and humanity, being the efficient cause of evil/sin, is guilty.

One might argue that “Freedom is not possible due to God having foreknowledge. Whether

freedom be defined as power to contrary or self-determination, the creature is certain to

choose what God has already known and, therefore, cannot be free in any sense. A

deterministic or even fatalistic view of God and his creation is the only possible alternative,

given the infallible foreknowledge of God.” Once again, the Bishop of Hippo provides a great

deal of aid in understanding the compatibility of divine foreknowledge and human freedom

(either definition).

In De Libero Arbitrio Evodius asks Augustine, “Since God foreknew that man would sin, that

which God foreknew must come to pass. How then is the will free when there is apparently

this unavoidable necessity?”28 Augustine is quick to point out the disjunctive thinking on the

matter. First, it assumes an either/or scenario (bifurcation) and doesn’t offer a third

alternative, viz., that God has foreknowledge of the power to will. Second, this disjunction

assumes, unnecessarily so, that foreknowledge is somehow causative. Once again, this

confuses conditions with causes.

Third, it makes foreknowledge out to be far more than is intended at this point. Augustine

clearly states that foreknowledge is prescience, or knowing beforehand. “God by his

foreknowledge does not use compulsion in the case of future events . . . God has

foreknowledge of all his own actions, but is not the agent of all that he foreknows . . . he has

no responsibility for the future actions of men though he knows them beforehand.”29 God

foreknew, for example, in 1899 that scores of Kosovo inhabitants would be brutely murdered in

1999. This knowledge does not implicate God as responsible.

The dilemma of foreknowledge and freedom has, for more than 17 centuries, troubled

philosophers and theologians to their grave and, no doubt, will continue to do so.30 Central to

both foreknowledge and freedom are (1) the infallible knowledge of God and (2) some idea of

human freedom other than a hard determinism.

Closely related to this problem is the question of God’s relationship to time. There is a sense in

which one cannot begin to wrestle with the dilemma of foreknowledge and freedom until the

issue of God’s relationship to time is resolved. The simplest form of the equation would be to

hold that God is timeless, which appears to be Augustine’s view.

For He [God] does not pass from this to that by transition of thought, but beholds

all things with absolute unchangeableness; so that of those things which emerge

in time, the future, indeed are not yet, and the present are now, and the past no

longer are; but all of these are by Him comprehended in His stable and eternal

presence.31

Certainly it would seem that if God has knowledge of all free choices, past, present and

future, then he would have to have a vantage point outside of time in order to not be

constrained by sequence. On this, Geisler is correct in saying that “God knows everything in

the eternal present but He does not know everything as the present moment in time; He

knows the past as past, the future as future, etc.”32 [italics his]. Therefore, it could be said

that God knows all things a priori, yet sees them as a posteriori.

But how does this position on foreknowledge and freedom cohere with Augustine’s view of

salvation? If it is true that God’s foreknowledge does not cause free decisions and humans are

incapable of coming to God on their own, how does anyone enter into the kingdom? At this

point it would be helpful to distinguish different categories of causes.

Aristotle points to four kinds of causes for any given effect: (1) material, (2) efficient, (3)

formal and (4) final or ultimate. God is the final or ultimate cause of all things but not the

material or efficient cause of all things. Put simply, God efficiently, materially and ultimately

causes regeneration of the soul. He creates the conditions under which humans can freely

love him (freedom = the material cause), lovingly persuades some to believe (enabling grace =

the efficient cause) and carries them on to completion in the eternal state (gift of

perseverance = final or ultimate cause).

Augustine, throughout his writings, exonerates God of being the efficient cause of evil. That

God decrees, in an ultimate sense, the means and the ends does not entail him being

responsible for them.33 Application of a singular causality principle to the metaphysical

problem of freedom and evil is short-sighted, not to mention an informal fallacy.

That freedom is, in itself, a good thing given by God to the creature. Augustine states “free

will, . . . is a good thing divinely bestowed, and that those are to be condemned who make a

bad use of it.”34 The cause of human freedom is God, yet the cause of sin and evil is the use

of freedom, which is in accordance with the antecedent inclination of the will. Augustine

illustrates the responsible/irresponsible use of a good thing.

If you see a man without feet you will admit that, from the point of view of the

wholeness of his body, a very great good is wanting. And yet you would not deny

that a man makes a bad use of his feet who uses them to hurt another or to

dishonour himself.35

Due to a sinful disposition or the bias toward evil no one can, apart from God’s intervening

grace, choose to enter the kingdom. “Good works do not produce grace but are produced by

grace.”36 And “calling [by God] precedes the good will . . . without his calling we cannot even

will.”37

Though God’s foreknowledge includes all free decisions, he does not share responsibility for

them all. God is no more responsible for the misuse of freedom any more than the giver of a

gift is responsible for how the gift is used. For example, one might receive a gift of $1,000 to

be used in helping an orphanage. If a high-powered rifle were instead purchased, then used to

assassinate the President of the United States this in no way implicates any guilt on the part

of the giver. Likewise, God gives the gift of freedom (and all things, for that matter), but he is

not morally responsible for how it is used (cf., 1 Cor. 4:7b).

God is behind all free decisions in an ultimate sense, behind free decisions in salvation in an

efficient sense and behind free decisions unto reprobation only in a material sense.

Consequently, “it is far from the truth that the sins of the creature must be attributed to the

Creator, even though those things must necessarily happen which he has foreknown.”38 The

ability to believe is the material cause of salvation.

For the effectiveness of God’s mercy cannot be in the power of man to frustrate,

if he will have none of it. If God wills to have mercy on men, he can call them in a

way that is suited to them, so that they will be moved to understand and to

follow . . . it is false to say that “it is not of God who hath mercy but of man who

willeth and runneth,” because God has mercy on no man in vain. He calls the man

on whom he has mercy in the way he knows will suit him, so that he will not

refuse the call [italics mine].39

God’s decrees do not entail him being the material, efficient, formal and final cause of

everything. It would be tantamount to blasphemy to assert that the perfect, holy and just

God is the author of evil or sin. Evil is a deprivation or a lack of something that ought to have

been otherwise. The lack of sight is, for a person, an evil whereas it isn’t for a tree. When the

Bible speaks of God creating disaster or clamity (evil in Hebrew, cf., Is. 45:7) it is in the

context of divine judgment upon a nation who ought to have behaved otherwise. He is the

efficient cause of judgment upon sin!

One other aspect of God’s omniscience must be broached as it relates to human freedom. This

is probably one of the most controversial facets of divine omniscience. It has been called

various things such as contingent knowledge or middle knowledge. Put simply, God knows not

only what will occur at all times by all people, but he knows what might occur given other

variables which may have been different. If God’s knowledge of all things actual and possible is

simultaneous, then middle knowledge is nothing more than a heuristic means for understanding

the logical processes of God’s thought. Whether or not Augustine held to any kind of middle

(or contingent) knowledge of God is difficult to know. It is only mentioned to illustrate the

scope of possible relationships between God’s knowledge and human choices. Craig says:

Since God knows what any free creature would do in any situation, he can, by

creating the appropriate situations, bring it about that creatures will achieve his

ends and purposes and that they will do so freely . . . Only an infinite Mind could

calculate the unimaginably complex and numerous factors that would need to be

combined in order to bring about through the free decisions of creatures a single

human event.40

Middle knowledge could serve to bridge the gap between God knowing all things simultaneously

and the order of events which occur in the world that God foreknows will happen.

Moreover, there are other kinds of relationships between subject and object than merely

cause/effect. Craig demonstrates the difference between cause/effect and

ground/consequent relationships that clearly show God’s foreknowledge of future events is not

causative. He does this by suggesting that God foreknows x, because x will take place.

The word because here indicates a logical, not a causal relation, one similar to

that expressed in the sentence ‘four is an even number because it is divisible by

two.’ The word because expresses a logical relation of ground and consequent.

God’s foreknowledge is chronologically prior to [x], but [x] is logically prior to God’s

foreknowledge.41

But this argument is a double-edged sword. If God foreknows x because it will take place,

then is it not equally true that x will take place because God foreknows it, given the same

relationship (i.e., ground/consequent) exists? In other words, the ground or basis upon which

free choices are made is God’s infallible foreknowledge and free human choices are the

consequent. God’s foreknowledge may be chronologically prior to the actualizing of a free

choice, but this in no way makes his foreknowledge contingent. Otherwise, he makes decisions

in the dark (cf., Eph. 1:11)!

Election and the sovereignty of God demonstrate that he uses the perdition of some as a

general deterrent from sin and the salvation of some as a general incentive for salvation (cf.,

Rom. 9:10-29). “The hardening of the ungodly demonstrates two things ? that a man should

fear and turn to God in piety, and that thanks should be given for his mercy to God

Bibliography

1.”On Free Will,” Book 1, 15, 34, Book II, 1, 1; trans. J.H.S. Burleigh, in The Library of

Christian Classics, ed. John Baillie, John T. McNeill and Henry P. Van Dusen, hereafter

called AEW, Augustine: EarlierWritings, (Philadelphia: Westminster), 108.

2.Cf., “The Spirit and the Letter,” introduction by John Burnaby, trans. John Burnaby, in

The Library of Christian Classics, ed. John Baillic, John T. McNeill and Henry P. Van

Dusen, hereafter called ALW, Augustine: Later Works, (Philadelphia: Westminster), 182.

3.Gordon R. Lewis and Bruce A. Demarest, Integrative Theology, vol. 2 (Grand Rapids:

Zondervan, 1990), 184.

4.Augustine, The City of God, XIX, 3, quoted in John W. Cooper, Body Soul and Life

Everlasting, (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1989), 11.

5.Augustine, On the Greatness of the Soul, Mll, 22, in Cooper, ibid.

6.”On Free Will,” Book III, xv, 46; AEW, 199.

7.Ibid., 200.

8.D. A. Carson, How Long, O Lord (Grand Rapids: Baker, 1990), 214-215.

9.Alvin Plantinga, God, Freedom and Evil (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1974), 29.

10.Lewis and Demarest, Integrative, vol. 2, 96.

11.”On Free Will,” Book III, xviii, 54; AEW, 202.

12.Philip Schaff, History of the Christian Church, vol. 3, Nicene and Post-Nicene

Christianity, (Grand Rapids: Ecrdmans, 1910), 819.

13.”On Free Will,” Book III, xvii, 52; AEW, III.

14.William G.T. Shedd, Dogmatic Theology, vol. 2, (Grand Rapids: Zondervan, n.d.), 113.

15.Philip Schaff, History, 819.

16.Gordon R. Lewis, “Faith and Rcason in the Thought of St. Augustine,” Ph.D. dissertation,

(Syracuse University, 1959), 81.

17.”The Spirit and the Letter,” xxvi, 43 -45, ALW, 226-229.

18.”Grace and Free Will,” 14, 27; trans. Robert P. Russell, in The Fathers of the Church,

vol. 59, ed. Roy Joscph Deferrari, hereafter called GFW, (Washington: Catholic University

of America Press, 1968), 280.

19. Ibid., 285.

20. Ibid., 289.

21.”The Trinity,” ALW, 23, 122.

22.William G.T. Shedd, Dogmatic Theology, vol. 2, (Grand Rapids: Zondervan, n.d.),

113-114.

23.Lewis and Demarest, Integrative, vol. 2, 96.

24.On Free Will,” Book III, x, 29; AEW, 189.

25.Ibid., xxii, 63, 209.

26.Ibid., xxii, 65, 2 1 0.

27.Ibid.

28.Ibid., Book 111, ii, 4, 172.

29.Ibid., iv, 11, 177.

30.For a brief history of the problem see Linda Zagzebski, The Dilemma of Freedom and

Foreknowledge (New York: Oxford University Press, 1991), note 1, chapter 1, 189.

31.The City of God,” XI, 2 1, trans. Marcus Dods (New York: The Modem Library, 1950),

364. For an alternative view which holds that God’s relationship to time changed when

time came into existence see William L. Craig, “God, Time and Eternity” Religious Studies

14 (1978): 497-503.

32.Norman L. Geisler, Philosophy of Religion (Grand Rapids: Zondervan, n.d.), note 10,

chapter 14, 331.

33.Cf., Lewis and Demarest, Integrative, vol. 1, op. cit., 310-328.

34. On Free Will,” Book II, xv, 48, AEW, 166.

35. Ibid.

36.”The Simplican,” The Second Question, 3, ALW, 388.

37.Ibid., 12, op. cit., 394-395.

38.AEW, Book III, vi, 18,181.

39.”The Simplican,” The Second Question, 13, ALW, 395.

40.William L. Craig, The Only Wise God (Grand Rapids: Baker, 1987), 135. Though Craig

holds to fallen creatures having power to contrary, it is likely that middle knowledge is

still possible given the alternative view of freedom offered here (viz.,