Смекни!
smekni.com

Bentham By John Stuart Mill Essay Research (стр. 2 из 4)

science; and the absence of which made those departments of

inquiry, as physics had been before Bacon, a field of

interminable discussion, leading to no result. It was not his

opinions, in short, but his method, that constituted the novelty

and the value of what he did; a value beyond all price, even

though we should reject the whole, as we unquestionably must a

large part, of the opinions themselves.

Bentham’s method may be shortly described as the method of

detail; of treating wholes by separating them into their parts,

abstractions by resolving them into Things, classes and

generalities by distinguishing them into the individuals of which

they are made up; and breaking every question into pieces before

attempting to solve it. The precise amount of originality of this

process, considered as a logical conception — its degree of

connexion with the methods of physical science, or with the

previous labours of Bacon, Hobbes or Locke — is not an essential

consideration in this pace. Whatever originality there was in the

method — in the subjects he applied it to, and in the rigidity

with which he adhered to it, there was the greatest. Hence his

interminable classifications. Hence his elaborate demonstrations

of the most acknowledged truths. That murder, incendiarism,

robbery, are mischievous actions, he will not take for granted

without proof; let the thing appear ever so self-evident, he will

know the why and the how of it with the last degree of precision;

he will distinguish all the different mischiefs of a crime,

whether of the first, the second or the third order, namely, 1.

the evil to the sufferer, and to his personal connexions; 2. the

danger from example, and the alarm or painful feeling of

insecurity; and 3. the discouragement to industry and useful

pursuits arising from the alarm, and the trouble and resources

which must be expended in warding off the danger. After this

enumeration, he will prove from the laws of human feeling, that

even the first of these evils, the sufferings of the immediate

victim, will on the average greatly outweigh the pleasure reaped

by the offender; much more when all the other evils are taken

into account. Unless this could be proved, he would account the

infliction of punishment unwarrantable; and for taking the

trouble to prove it formally, his defence is, ‘there are truths

which it is necessary to prove, not for their own sakes, because

they are acknowledged, but that an opening may be made for the

reception of other truths which depend upon them. It is in this

manner we provide for the reception of first principles, which,

once received, prepare the way for admission of all other

truths.’ To which may be added, that in this manner also we

discipline the mind for practising the same sort of dissection

upon questions more complicated and of more doubtful issue.

It is a sound maxim, and one which all close thinkers have

felt, but which no one before Bentham ever so consistently

applied, that error lurks in generalities: that the human mind is

not capable of embracing a complex whole, until it has surveyed

and catalogued the parts of which that whole is made up; that

abstractions are not realities per se, but an abridged mode of

expressing facts, and that the only practical mode of dealing

with them is to trace them back to the facts (whether of

experience or of consciousness) of which they are the expression.

Proceeding on this principle, Bentham makes short work with the

ordinary modes of moral and political reasoning. These, it

appeared to him, when hunted to their source, for the most part

terminated in phrases. In politics, liberty, social order,

constitution, law of nature, social compact, etc., were the

catchwords: ethics had its analogous ones. Such were the

arguments on which the gravest questions of morality and policy

were made to turn; not reasons, but allusions to reasons;

sacramental expressions, by which a summary appeal was made to

some general sentiment of mankind, or to some maxim in familiar

use, which might be true or not, but the limitations of which no

one had ever critically examined. And this satisfied other

people; but not Bentham. He required something more than opinion

as a reason for opinion. Whenever he found a phrase used as an

argument for or against anything, he insisted upon knowing what

it meant; whether it appealed to any standard, or gave intimation

of any matter of fact relevant to the question; and if he could

not find that it did either, he treated it as an attempt on the

part of the disputant to impose his own individual sentiment on

other people, without giving them a reason for it; a ‘

contrivance for avoiding the obligation of appealing to any

external standard, and for prevailing upon the reader to accept

of the author’s sentiment and opinion as a reason, and that a

sufficient one, for itself. Bentham shall speak for himself on

this subject: the passage is from his first systematic work,

‘Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation’, and

we could scarcely quote anything more strongly exemplifying both

the strength and weakness of his mode of philosophizing.

It is curious enough to observe the variety of inventions men

have hit upon, and the variety of phrases they have brought

forward, in order to conceal from the world, and, if possible,

from themselves, this very general and therefore very pardonable

self-sufficiency.

1. One man says, he has a thing made on purpose to tell him

what is right and what is wrong; and that is called a ‘moral

sense’.. and then he goes to work at his ease, and says, such a

thing is right, and such a thing is wrong — why? ‘Because my

moral sense tells me it is.’

2. Another man comes and alters the phrase: leaving out

moral, and putting in common in the room of it. He then tells you

that his common sense tells him what is right and wrong, as

surely as the other’s moral sense did; meaning by common sense a

sense of some kind or other, which, he says, is possessed by all

mankind: the sense of those whose sense is not the same as the

author’s being struck out as not worth taking. This contrivance

does better than the other; for a moral sense being a new thing,

a man may feel about him a good while without being able to find

it out: but common sense is as old as the creation; and there is

no man but would be ashamed to be thought not to have as much of

it as his neighbours. It has another great advantage: by

appearing to share power, it lessens envy; for when a man gets up

upon this ground, in order to anathematize those who differ from

him, it is not by a sic volo sic jubeo, but by a velitis

jubeatis.

3. Another man comes, and says, that as to a moral sense

indeed, he cannot find that he has any such thing: that, however,

he has an understanding, which will do quite as well. This

understanding, he says, is the standard of right and wrong: it

tells him so and so. All good and wise men understand as he does:

if other men’s understandings differ in any part from his, so

much the worse for them: it is a sure sign they are either

defective or corrupt.

4. Another man says, that there is an eternal and immutable

Rule of Right: that the rule of right dictates so and so: and

then he begins giving you his sentiments upon anything that comes

uppermost: and these sentiments (you are to take for granted) are

so many branches of the eternal rule of right.

5. Another man, or perhaps the same man (it is nO matter),

says that there are certain practices conformable and others

repugnant, to the Fitness of Things; and then he tells you, at

his leisure, what practices are conformable, and what repugnant:

just as he happens to like a practice or dislike it.

6. A great multitude of people are continually talking of the

Law of Nature; and then they go on giving you their sentiments

about what is right and what is wrong: and these sentiments, you

are to understand, are so many chapters and sections of the Law

of Nature.

7. Instead of the phrase, Law of Nature, you have sometimes

Law of Reason, Right Reason, Natural Justice, Natural Equity,

Good Order. Any of them will do equally well. This latter is most

used in politics. The three last are much more tolerable than the

others, because they do not very explicitly claim to be anything

more than phrases: they insist but feebly upon their being looked

upon as so many positive standards of themselves, and seem

content to be taken, upon occasion, for phrases expressive of the

conformity of the thing in question to the proper standards,

whatever that may be. On most occasions, however, it will be

better to say utility. utility is clearer as referring more

explicitly to pain and pleasure.

8. We have one philosopher, who says, there is no harm in

anything in the world but in telling a lie; and that if, for

example, you were to murder your own father, this would only be a

particular way of saying, he was not your father. Of course when

this philosopher sees anything that he does not like, he says, it

is a particular way of telling a lie. It is saying, that the act

ought to be done, or may be done, when, in truth, it ought not be

done.

9. The fairest and openest of them all is that sort of man

who speaks out, and says, I am of the number of the Elect: now

God himself takes care to inform the Elect what is right: and

that with so good effect, and let them strive ever so, they

cannot help not only knowing it but practising it. If therefore a

man wants to know what is right and what is wrong, he has nothing

to do but to come to me.

Few will contend that this is a perfectly fair representation

of the animus of those who employ the various phrases so

amusingly animadverted on; but that the phrases contain no

argument, save what is grounded on the very feelings they are

adduced to justify, is a truth which Bentham had the eminent

merit of first pointing out.

It is the introduction into the philosophy of human conduct,

of this method of detail — of this practice of never reasoning

about wholes until they have been resolved into their parts, nor

about abstractions until they have been translated into realities

– that constitutes the originality of Bentham in philosophy, and

makes him the great reformer of the moral and political branch of

it. To what he terms the ‘exhaustive method of classification’,

which is but one branch of this more general method, he himself

ascribes everything original in the systematic and elaborate work

from which we have quoted. The generalities of his philosophy

itself have little or no novelty: to ascribe any to the doctrine

that general utility is the foundation of morality, would imply

great ignorance of the history of philosophy, of general

literature, and of Bentham’s own writings. He derived the idea,

as he says himself, from Helvetius; and it was the doctrine no

less, of the religious philosophers of that age, prior to Reid

and Beattie. We never saw an abler defence of the doctrine of

utility than in a book written in refutation of Shaftesbury, and

now little read — Brown’s ‘Essays on the Characteristics’; and

in Johnson’s celebrated review of Soame Jenyns, the same doctrine

is set forth as that both of the author and of the reviewer. In

all ages of philosophy one of its schools has been utilitarian –

not only from the time of Epicurus, but long before. It was by

mere accident that this opinion became connected in Bentham with

his peculiar method. The utilitarian philosophers antecedent to

him had no more claims to the method than their antagonists. To

refer, for instance, to the Epicurean philosophy, according to

the most complete view we have of the moral part of it, by the

most accomplished scholar of antiquity, Cicero; we ask any one

who has read his philosophical writings, the ‘De Finibus’ for

instance, whether the arguments of the Epicureans do not, just as

much as those of the Stoics or Platonists, consist of mere

rhetorical appeals to common notions, to eikita and simeia

instead of tekmiria, notions picked up as it were casually, and

when true at all, never so narrowly looked into as to ascertain

in what sense and under what limitations they are true. The

application of a real inductive philosophy to the problems of

ethics, is as unknown to the Epicurean moralists as to any of the

other schools; they never take a question to pieces, and join

issue on a definite point. Bentham certainly did not learn his

sifting and anatomizing method from them.

This method Bentham has finally installed in philosophy; has

made it henceforth imperative on philosophers of all schools. By

it he has formed the intellects of many thinkers, who either

never adopted, or have abandoned, many of his peculiar opinions.

He has taught the method to men of the most opposite schools to

his; he has made them perceive that if they do not test their

doctrines by the method of detail, their adversaries will. He has

thus, it is not too much to say, for the first time introduced

precision of thought into moral and political philosophy. Instead

of taking up their opinions by intuition, or by ratiocination

from premises adopted on a mere rough view, and couched in

language so vague that it is impossible to say exactly whether

they are true or false, philosophers are now forced to understand

one another, to break down the generality of their propositions,

and join a precise issue in every dispute. This is nothing less

than a revolution in philosophy. Its effect is gradually becoming

evident in the writings of English thinkers of every variety of

opinion, and will be felt more and more in proportion as

Bentham’s writings are diffused, and as the number of minds to

whose formation they contribute is multiplied.

It will naturally be presumed that of the fruits of this

great philosophical improvement some portion at least will have

been reaped by its author. Armed with such a potent instrument,

and wielding it with such singleness of aim; cultivating the

field of practical philosophy with such unwearied and such

consistent use of a method right in itself, and not adopted by

his predecessors; it cannot he but that Bentham by his own

inquiries must have accomplished something considerable. And so,

it will be found, he has; something not only considerable, but

extraordinary; though but little compared with what he has left

undone, and far short of what his sanguine and almost boyish

fancy made him flatter himself that he had accomplished. His

peculiar method, admirably calculated to make clear thinkers, and

sure ones to the extent of their materials, has not equal

efficacy for making those materials complete. It is a security

for accuracy, but not for comprehensiveness; or rather, it is a

security for one sort of comprehensiveness, but not for another.

Bentham’s method of laying out his subject is admirable as a

preservative against one kind of narrow and partial views. He

begins by placing before himself the whole of the field of

inquiry to which the particular question belongs, and divides

down till he arrives at the thing he is in search of; and thus by

successively rejecting all which is not the thing, he gradually

works out a definition of what it is. This, which he calls the

exhaustive method, is as old as philosophy itself. Plato owes

everything to it, and does everything by it; and the use made of

it by that great man in his Dialogues, Bacon, in one of those

pregnant logical hints scattered through his writings, and so

much neglected by most of his pretended followers, pronounces to

be the nearest approach to a true inductive method in the ancient

philosophy. Bentham was probably not aware that Plato had

anticipated him in the process to which he too declared that he

owed everything. By the practice of it, his speculations are

rendered eminently systematic and consistent; no question, with

him, is ever an insulated one; he sees every subject in connexion

with all the other subjects with which in his view it is related,

and from which it requires to be distinguished; and as all that

he knows, in the least degree allied to the subject, has been