Смекни!
smekni.com

Bentham By John Stuart Mill Essay Research (стр. 4 из 4)

devotional feeling under that of sympathy with God. But the whole

of the impelling or restraining principles, whether of this or of

another world, which he recognizes, are either self-love, or love

or hatred towards other sentient beings. That there might be no

doubt of what he thought on the subject, he has not left us to

the general evidence of his writings, but has drawn out a ‘Table

of the Springs of Action’, an express enumeration and

classification of human motives, with their various names,

laudatory, vituperative, and neutral: and this table, to be found

in Part I of his collected works, we recommend to the study of

those who would understand his philosophy.

Man is never recognized by him as a being capable of pursuing

spiritual perfection as an end; of desiring, for its own sake,

the conformity of his own character to his standard of

excellence, without hope of good or fear of evil from other

source than his own inward consciousness. Even in the more

limited form of Conscience, this great fact in human nature

escapes him. Nothing is more curious than the absence of

recognition in any of his writings of the existence of

conscience, as a thing distinct from philanthropy, from affection

for God or man, and from self-interest in this world or in the

next. There is a studied abstinence from any of the phrases

which, in the mouths of others, import the acknowledgment of such

a fact. If we find the words ‘Conscience’, ‘Principle’, ‘Moral

Rectitude’, ‘Moral Duty’, in his Table of the Springs of Action,

it is among the synonymes of the ‘love of reputation’. with an

intimation as to the two former phrases, that they are also

sometimes synonymous with the religious motive, or the motive of

sympathy. The feeling of moral approbation or disapprobation

properly so called, either towards ourselves or our

fellow-creatures, he seems unaware of the existence of; and

neither the word self-respect, nor the idea to which that word is

appropriated, occurs even once, so far as our recollection serves

us, in his whole writings.

Nor is it only the moral part of man’s nature, in the strict

sense of the term — the desire of perfection, or the feeling of

an approving or of an accusing conscience — that he overlooks;

he but faintly recognizes, as a fact in human nature, the pursuit

of any other ideal end for its own sake. The sense of honour, and

personal dignity — that feeling of personal exaltation and

degradation which acts independently of other people’s opinion,

or even in defiance of it; the love of beauty, the passion of the

artist; the love of order, of congruity, of consistency in all

things, and conformity to their end; the love of power, not in

the limited form of power over other human beings, but abstract

power, the power of making our volitions effectual; the love of

action, the thirst for movement and activity, a principle

scarcely of less influence in human life than its opposite, the

love of ease: None of these powerful constituents of human nature

are thought worthy of a place among the ‘Springs of Action’; and

though there is possibly no one of them of the existence of which

an acknowledgment might not be found in some corner of Bentham’s

writings, no conclusions are ever founded on the acknowledgment.

Man, that most complex being, is a very simple one in his eyes.

Even under the head of sympathy, his recognition does not extend

to the more complex forms of the feeling — the love of loving,

the need of a sympathizing support, or of objects of admiration

and reverence. If he thought at all of any of the deeper feelings

of human nature, it was but as idiosyncrasies of taste, with

which the moralist no more than the legislator had any concern,

further than to prohibit such as were mischievous among the

actions to which they might chance to lead. To say either that

man should, or that he should not, take pleasure in one thing,

displeasure in another, appeared to him as much an act of

despotism in the moralist as in the political ruler.

It would be most unjust to Bentham to surmise (as

narrow-minded and passionate adversaries are apt in such cases to

do) that this picture of human nature was copied from himself;

that all those constituents of humanity which he rejected from

his table of motives, were wanting in his own breast. The unusual

strength of his early feelings of virtue, was, as we have seen,

the original cause of all his speculations; and a noble sense of

morality, and especially of justice, guides and pervades them

all. But having been early accustomed to keep before his mind’s

eye the happiness of mankind (or rather of the whole sentient

world), as the only thing desirable in itself, or which rendered

anything else desirable, he confounded all disinterested feelings

which he found in himself, with the desire of general happiness:

just as some religious writers, who loved virtue for its own sake

as much perhaps as men could do, habitually confounded their love

of virtue with their fear of hell. It would have required greater

subtlety than Bentham possessed, to distinguish from each other,

feelings which, from long habit, always acted in the same

direction; and his want of imagination prevented him from reading

the distinction, where it is legible enough, in the hearts of

others.

Accordingly, he has not been followed in this grand oversight

by any of the able men who, from the extent of their intellectual

obligations to him, have been regarded as his disciples. They may

have followed him in his doctrine of utility, and in his

rejection of a moral sense as the test of right and wrong: but

while repudiating it as such, they have, with Hartley,

acknowledged it as a fact in human nature; they have endeavoured

to account for it, to assign its laws: nor are they justly

chargeable either with undervaluing this part of our nature, or

with any disposition to throw it into the background of their

speculations. If any part of the influence of this cardinal error

has extended itself to them, it is circuitously, and through the

effect on their minds of other parts of Bentham’s doctrines.

Sympathy, the only disinterested motive which Bentham

recognized, he felt the inadequacy of, except in certain limited

cases, as a security for virtuous action. Personal affection, he

well knew, is as liable to operate to the injury of third

parties, and requires as much to be kept under government, as any

other feeling whatever: and general philanthropy, considered as a

motive influencing mankind in general, he estimated at its true

value when divorced from the feeling of duty — as the very

weakest and most unsteady of all feelings. There remained, as a

motive by which mankind are influenced, and by which they may be

guided to their good, only personal interest. Accordingly,

Bentham’s idea of the world is that of a collection of persons

pursuing each his separate interest or pleasure, and the

prevention of whom from jostling one another more than is

unavoidable, may be attempted by hopes and fears derived from

three sources — the law, religion and public opinion. To these

three powers, considered as binding human conduct, he gave the

name of sanctions. the political sanction, operating by the

rewards and penalties of the law; the religious sanction, by

those expected from the Ruler of the Universe; and the popular

which he characteristically calls also the moral sanction,

operating through the pains and pleasures arising from the favour

or disfavour of our fellow-creatures.

Such is Bentham’s theory of the world. And now, in a spirit

neither of apology nor of censure, but of calm appreciation, we

are to inquire how far this view of human nature and life will

carry any one: how much it will accomplish in morals, and how

much in political and social philosophy: what it will do for the

individual, and what for society.

It will do nothing for the conduct of the individual, beyond

prescribing some of the more obvious dictates of worldly

prudence, and outward probity and beneficence. There is no need

to expatiate on the deficiencies of a system of ethics which does

not pretend to aid individuals in the formation of their own

character. which recognizes no such wish as that of self culture,

we may even say no such power, as existing in human nature; and

if it did recognize, could furnish little assistance to that

great duty, because it overlooks the existence of about half of

the whole number of mental feelings which human beings are

capable of, including all those of which the direct objects are

states of their own mind.

Morality consists of two parts. One of these is

self-education; the training, by the human being himself, of his

affections and will. That department is a blank in Bentham’s

system. The other and co-equal part, the regulation of his

outward actions, must be altogether halting and imperfect without

the first; for how can we judge in what manner many an action

will affect even the worldly interests of ourselves or others,

unless we take in, as part of the question, its influence on the

regulation of our, or their, affections and desires? A moralist

on Bentham’s principles may get as far as this, that he ought not

to slay, burn, or steal; but what will be his qualifications for

regulating the nicer shades of human behaviour, or for laying

down even the greater moralities as to those facts in human life

which tend to influence the depths of the character quite

independently of any influence on worldly circumstances — such,

for instance, as the sexual relations, or those of family in

general, or any other social and sympathetic connexions of an

intimate kind? The moralities of these questions depend

essentially on considerations which Bentham never so much as took

into the account; and when he happened to be in the right, it was

always, and necessarily, on wrong or insufficient grounds.

It is fortunate for the world that Bentham’s taste lay rather

in the direction of jurisprudential than of properly ethical

inquiry. Nothing expressly of the latter kind has been published

under his name, except the ‘Deontology’ — a book scarcely ever,

in our experience, alluded to by any admirer of Bentham without

deep regret that it ever saw the light. We did not expect from

Bentham correct systematic views of ethics, or a sound treatment

of any question the moralities of which require a profound

knowledge of the human heart; but we did anticipate that the

greater moral questions would have been boldly plunged into, and

at least a searching criticism produced of the received opinions;

we did not expect that the petite morale almost alone would have

been treated, and that with the most pedantic minuteness, and on

the quid pro quo principles which regulate trade. The book has

not even the value which would belong to an authentic exhibition

of the legitimate consequences of an erroneous line of thought;

for the style proves it to have been so entirely rewritten, that

it is impossible to tell how much or how little of it is

Bentham’s. The collected edition, now in progress, will not, it

is said, include Bentham’s religious writings; these, although we

think most of them of exceedingly small value, are at least his,

and the world has a right to whatever light they throw upon the

constitution of his mind. But the omission of the ‘Deontology’

would be an act of editorial discretion which we should seem

entirely justifiable.

If Bentham’s theory of life can do so little for the

individual, what can it do for society?

It will enable a society which has attained a certain state

of spiritual development, and the maintenance of which in that

state is otherwise provided for, to prescribe the rules by which

it may protect its material interests. It will do nothing (except

sometimes as an instrument in the hands of a higher doctrine) for

the spiritual interests of society; nor does it suffice of itself

even for the material interests. That which alone causes any

material interests to exist, which alone enables any body of

human beings to exist as a society, is national character: that

it is, which causes one nation to succeed in what it attempts,

another to fail; one nation to understand and aspire to elevated

things, another to grovel in mean ones; which makes the greatness

of one nation lasting, and dooms another to early and rapid

decay. The true teacher of the fitting social arrangements for

England, France, or America, is the one who can point out how the

English, French or American character can be improved, and how it

has been made what it is. A philosophy of laws and institutions,

not founded on a philosophy of national character, is an

absurdity. But what could Bentham’s opinion be worth on national

character? How could he, whose mind contained so few and so poor

types of individual character, rise to that higher

generalization? All he can do is but to indicate means by which,

in any given state of the national mind, the material interests

of society can be protected; saving the question, of which others

must judge, whether the use of those means would have, on the

national character, any injurious influence.

We have arrived, then, at a sort of estimate of what a

philosophy like Bentham’s can do. It can teach the means of

organizing and regulating the merely business part of the social

arrangements. Whatever can be understood or whatever done without

reference to moral influences, his philosophy is equal to; where

those influences require to be taken into account, it is at

fault. He committed the mistake of supposing that the business

part of human affairs was the whole of them; all at least that

the legislator and the moralist had to do with. Not that he

disregarded moral influences when he perceived them; but his want

of imagination, small experience of human feelings, and ignorance

of the filiation and connexion of feelings with one another, made

this rarely the case.

The business part is accordingly the only province of human

affairs which Bentham has cultivated with any success; into which

he had introduced any considerable number of comprehensive and

luminous practical principles. That is the field of his

greatness; and there he is indeed great. He has swept away the

accumulated cobwebs of centuries — he has untied knots which the

efforts of the ablest thinkers, age after age, had only drawn

tighter; and it is not exaggeration to say of him that over a

great part of the field he was the first to shed the light of

reason.

We turn with pleasure from what Bentham could not do, to what

he did. It is an ungracious task to call a great benefactor of

mankind to account for not being a greater — to insist upon the

errors of a man who has originated more new truths, has given to

the world more sound practical lessons, than it ever received,

except in a few glorious instances, from any other individual.

The unpleasing part of our work is ended. We are now to show the

greatness of the man; the grasp which his intellect took of the

subjects with which it was fitted to deal; the giant’s task which

was before him, and the hero’s courage and strength with which he

achieved it. Nor let that which he did be deemed of small account

because its province was limited: man has but the choice to go a

little way in many paths, or a great way in only one. The field

of Bentham’s labours was like the space between two parallel

lines; narrow to excess in one direction, in another it reached

to infinity.

Bentham’s speculations, as we are already aware, began with

law; and in that department he accomplished his greatest

triumphs. He found the philosophy of law a chaos, he left it a

science; he found the practice of the law an Augean stable, he

turned the river into it which is mining and sweeping away mound

after mound of its rubbish.

Without joining in the exaggerated invectives against

lawyers, which Bentham sometimes permitted to himself, or making

one portion of society alone accountable for the fault of all, we

may say that circumstances had made English lawyers in a peculiar

degree liable to the reproach of Voltaire, who defines lawyers

the ‘conservators of ancient barbarous usages’. The basis of the

En